Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian
Philosophers Philosophers
Volume 39 Issue 4 Article 5
10-1-2022
A Holistic Response to the Problem of Evil A Holistic Response to the Problem of Evil
Jonathan Fuqua
Conception Seminary College
Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy
Recommended Citation Recommended Citation
Fuqua, Jonathan (2022) "A Holistic Response to the Problem of Evil,"
Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the
Society of Christian Philosophers
: Vol. 39: Iss. 4, Article 5.
DOI: 10.37977/faithphil.2022.39.4.5
Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol39/iss4/5
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative
exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian
Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange.
FAITH AND PHILOSOPHY Vol. 39 No. 4 October 2022
doi: 10.37977/faithphil.2022.39.4.5
All rights reserved
pp.593–613
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO THE PROBLEM OF EVIL
Jonathan Fuqua
The four standard theistic responses to the evidential problem of evil are
theodicy, Reformed Epistemology, natural theology, and skeptical theism.
It’s somewhat common for theists to combine Reformed Epistemology and
skeptical theism or natural theology and theodicy. An insufciently appre-
ciated possibility is that of combining all four of these positions into a more
holistic response to the evidential problem of evil. The chief hurdle to doing
this is that it seems that skeptical theism isn’t compatible with either natural
theology or theodicy. This rst appearance, however, is misleading. And, in-
terestingly, certain theists have implicitly put forth a holistic response to the
problem of evil. In this paper, I sketch out how one can combine all four of
the standard theistic responses to the evidential problem of evil so as to yield
a holistic response to the problem of evil. The focus will be on reconciling
skeptical theism with natural theology and theodicy.
1. Introduction
Proponents of evidential arguments from evil argue that the facts of evil
are good evidence against the existence of God.
1
There are four standard
theistic responses to such arguments that are prevalent in the contempo-
rary literature on the problem of evil. First, some theists give theodicies,
stories intended to show how God can be justied in allowing the evil
1
In my view, the most potent version of the evidential argument from evil is to be found
in Draper, “Pain and Pleasure.” It is commonly believed that Pike’s “Hume on Evil” and
Plantinga’s The Nature of Necessity have defused the logical problem of evil. Draper, himself
a non-theist, says that “logical arguments from evil . . . are rejected by the vast majority
of contemporary philosophers of religion” and that “most philosophers nowadays believe”
that the logical incompatibility of God and evil “cannot be shown” (see Draper, “The Prob-
lem of Evil,” 335). For an overview of the logical problem of evil, see Howard-Snyder, “The
Logical Problem of Evil.” It must be noted, however, that the logical problem of evil has not
completely gone away. For a new presentation and defense of the logical problem of evil, see
Schellenberg, “A New Logical Problem of Evil,” and Sterba, Is a Good God Logically Possible?
For a response to Sterba, see Feser, “The Thomistic Dissolution of the Logical Problem of
Evil.”
Faith and Philosophy594
appealed to in the evidential argument under consideration.
2
A second
response is Reformed Epistemology, according to which theists enjoy, or
can enjoy, non-inferential justication for belief in God such that belief in
God can be justied even if theism might be unable to gain any positive
justicatory status from its ability to explain some body of data.
3
A third
theistic response is that of the natural theologian, who argues that any
negative evidence against theism that is provided by the data of evil is
outweighed by the positive evidence for theism to which the premises
of natural theological arguments appeal.
4
A fourth response is skeptical
theism, the core claim of which is that we are not in a position to say how
likely the facts of evil are given theism.
5
The thesis of this paper is that these four responses are not inconsistent
with each other. In the literature on the problem of evil, it is common to
take one of these responses and develop it in some level of detail. This
focused approach has the benet of allowing us to see just how helpful
(or not) a particular response to evidential arguments from evil can be.
It has the dialectical demerit, however, of tempting us to forget that in
actual practice many theists combine two or more of the four standard re-
sponses. It also has the demerit of hindering us from seeing just how bene-
cial it can be to combine multiple responses into a more holistic response
to the problem of evil. Theists thus typically employ a subpar strategy in
their published responses to evidential arguments from evil by focusing
on just one of the four standard responses. In this paper, I sketch a holistic
response to the problem of evil.
Many theists in the past, as well as today, have employed two or more
of the four standard theistic responses. According to Rudavsky, skeptical
theism has roots in Isaiah, Job, Paul, Plotinus, John Scotus Eriugena, Mai-
monides, Aquinas, and Descartes.
6
But, of course, some of these also did
2
See Murray, “Theodicy,” for an overview of the project of theodicy. The most inuential
big picture theodicy projects in the contemporary literature are probably those of Hick’s Evil
and the God of Love, Swinburne’s Providence and the Problem of Evil, and Stump’s Wandering in
Darkness.
3
For an overview of Reformed Epistemology, see Bergmann, “Rational Religious Belief
Without Argument” and “Reformed Epistemology.” See also Moon, “Recent Work in Re-
formed Epistemology.” Plantinga’s Warranted Christian Belief is of course the most extensive,
inuential, and important presentation of the Reformed Epistemology project. For a recent
defense of Plantinga’s religious epistemology, see McNabb, “Warranted Religion.”
4
An example of the natural theology response is provided by Swinburne’s The Existence of
God. For more cutting-edge natural theology, see Craig and Moreland, The Blackwell Compan-
ion to Natural Theology; Feser, Five Proofs of the Existence of God; and Walls and Dougherty, Two
Dozen (or so) Arguments for God. For an overview of the terrain, see Baker-Hytch, “Natural
Theology and Religious Belief.”
5
For overviews of skeptical theism, see Bergmann, “Skeptical Theism and the Problem
of Evil,” McBrayer, “Skeptical Theism,” and Dougherty, “Skeptical Theism.” My character-
ization of skeptical theism follows Draper’s characterization of the core claim of skeptical
theism; see Draper, “The Skeptical Theist,” 176.
6
Rudavsky, “A Brief History of Skeptical Responses to Evil.” For an in-depth look at Des-
cartes’s skeptical theism, see Robinson, “Descartes’s Sceptical Theism.”
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 595
natural theology, chief among them Aquinas and Descartes. Aquinas also
did theodicy
7
and, if Plantinga reads him correctly, also accepted the Re-
formed Epistemological view that it is possible to have non- inferentially
justied belief that God exists. So, it may well turn out that Aquinas him-
self utilized all four of the standard responses. And it certainly looks to me
as if Plantinga has made use of Reformed Epistemology, natural theology,
theodicy, and skeptical theism.
8
In short, I think some theists have been
implicitly employing a holistic or cumulative case approach; it would be
good to know if they are onto something. Of course, such a holistic re-
sponse can work only if each individual response is successful. Unfortu-
nately, I cannot defend each response here; my goal is simply to argue for
their compatibility. My task here is a second-order one: to argue for the
feasibility of a holistic response to the problem of evil.
9
2. Reformed Epistemology, Natural Theology, and Theodicy
In this section, I argue for the compatibility of Reformed Epistemology,
natural theology, and theodicy. Reformed Epistemology is the view that
theistic belief is or can be non-inferentially justied, that, as Bergmann
puts it, “belief in God—like the belief that I had orange juice for breakfast
or the belief that there’s a ball in front of me—can be properly basic.”
10
Natural theology is typically thought of as the activity of producing ar-
guments for God’s existence.
11
Natural theologians do assume—and seek
to show—that there is inferential justication or propositional evidence
for theism. Natural theology qua activity is compatible with Reformed
Epistemology derivatively, in the sense that the assumption which natu-
ral theologians make—that there is propositional evidence for theism—is
consistent with Reformed Epistemology.
Reformed Epistemology and natural theology are sometimes thought
of as rivals.
12
Reformed Epistemologists are sometimes suspicious of the
thought that theism should be understood as an explanatory hypothesis,
7
See Stump, “Aquinas on the Sufferings of Job.”
8
See the relevant chapters in Plantinga’s books The Nature of Necessity and Warranted
Christian Belief and his papers “On Being Evidentially Challenged” and “Supralapsarianism,
or ‘O Felix Culpa.’”
9
Thanks to a referee for some helpful comments on how to think about the nature of the
project of this paper.
10
Bergmann, “Rational Religious Belief Without Argument,” 538.
11
Thus:
Natural theology is the practice of philosophically reecting on the existence and
nature of God independent of real or apparent divine revelation or scripture. Tra-
ditionally, natural theology involves weighing arguments for and against God’s ex-
istence, and it is contrasted with revealed theology, which may be carried out within
the context of ostensible revelation or scripture. (Taliaferro, “The Project of Natural
Theology,” 1)
12
This is probably due, at least in part, to Plantinga’s paper, “The Reformed Objection to
Natural Theology.”
Faith and Philosophy596
a suspicion that seems uncongenial to natural theology.
13
When Reformed
Epistemologists voice this suspicion, they typically also argue that theistic
belief can be properly basic whether or not it enjoys the kind of proposi-
tional evidence championed by the natural theologian.
14
This latter notion
was, in fact, one of the main points of Plantinga’s 1967 book, God and Other
Minds, in which he argued that belief in God, like belief in other minds,
can be rational even if it can’t be established by philosophical proofs.
15
Additionally, a natural theologian may, if she likes, endorse the “hyperev-
identialist” view that if a theist has justied theistic belief, that is because
she has inferential support for that belief.
16
Such hyperevidentialism is
obviously incompatible with Reformed Epistemology.
Fortunately, Reformed Epistemology and natural theology are not, con-
trary to these initial appearances, incompatible. First, suspicion, or even
denial, that theism is an explanatory hypothesis is consistent with afrm-
ing the possibility of inferential support for theistic belief. This is an in-
stance of the more general principle that one can have non-inferential as
well as inferential support for a proposition that one does not construe
as an explanatory hypothesis. I might enjoy non-inferential justication
for the view that nonconsensual sex is wrong and also have an argument
that it is wrong without thereby understanding that proposition to be an
explanatory hypothesis. Similarly, rejection of the idea that theism is an
explanatory hypothesis does not, by itself, entail rejection of the natural
theology view that theism can enjoy inferential justicatory support.
Second, a natural theologian needn’t endorse hyperevidentialism. It’s
entirely possible for a proposition to enjoy inferential and non- inferential
support, to have both propositional and non-propositional evidence in
its favor. There is no reason a natural theologian cannot say that theism
has both kinds of justicatory support. Plantinga and Swinburne, the two
most prominent contemporary advocates of Reformed Epistemology and
natural theology, respectively, apparently concur. Plantinga, after all, is
known not only for developing a proper functionalist version of Reformed
Epistemology, but also for developing a modal version of the ontological
argument. Plantinga, additionally, is on record as saying that the ne-
tuning argument offers “mild support” for theism.
17
He has also, of course,
developed about two dozen arguments for theism in his “Two Dozen (or
so) Theistic Arguments.”
18
Plantinga has been careful to point out that the
13
For a critical discussion of the idea that God’s existence should be treated as an explan-
atory hypothesis, see Holley, “On Treating God’s Existence as an Explanatory Hypothesis.”
14
The most fully developed Reformed Epistemology currently on offer can be found in
Plantinga, Warranted Christian Belief.
15
See Plantinga, God and Other Minds.
16
This term comes from Dougherty and Tweedt, “Religious Epistemology,” 548ff.
17
Plantinga, Where the Conict Really Lies, 224.
18
See Plantinga, “Two Dozen (or so) Theistic Arguments.” For a recent collection of essays
on Plantinga’s two dozen (or so) theistic arguments, see Walls and Dougherty, Two Dozen (or
so) Arguments for God.
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 597
proper basicality of theistic belief is fully compatible with its also enjoying
support from theistic arguments, and in the preface to a revised edition
of God and Other Minds, written in 1990, he takes a much more optimistic
attitude toward natural theology than he did in 1967.
19
Swinburne also
argues that it is possible for religious believers to enjoy non-inferential
justication for theistic belief, suggesting that natural theology is, how-
ever, needed for those believers who are aware of atheistic arguments or
who have “no experiences of the apparent presence of God.”
20
Like Plant-
inga and Swinburne, I conclude that there is no inconsistency between
Reformed Epistemology and natural theology.
21
This compatibility strengthens the theist’s response to the problem of
evil. Assume that Reformed Epistemology is correct and that belief in God
can be non-inferentially justied. Assume also that there isn’t any, or any
signicant, propositional evidence for theism. Assume further that some
evidential argument from evil really does offer good propositional evidence
against theism. The Reformed Epistemologist will likely follow Plantinga
here and argue that theism can be both improbable on our propositional
evidence and justied on our non-propositional evidence.
22
Now, let’s
make some contrary assumptions: that there is no good non- propositional
evidence for theism, that some evidential argument from evil really does
offer good propositional evidence against theism, but that there are some
good natural theological arguments for God’s existence. In this case, while
theism might not be probable with respect to our non-propositional evi-
dence, and improbable with respect to one part of our propositional evi-
dence, the natural theologian will say that theism is more probable than
not (or probable enough to be rationally believed) given our total proposi-
tional evidence. Now, if Reformed Epistemology and natural theology are
both correct, then the theist can say that theism has good non-inferential
and inferential support, thus responding to the problem of evil by citing
two lines of justicatory support rather than just one.
This dual response to the problem of evil would be even stronger
if the theist could add theodicy to the mix. Let’s assume that there are
some good theodicies so that the only question is whether theodicy is
19
Plantinga, Where the Conict Really Lies, 179.
20
Swinburne, Faith and Reason, 90. Swinburne’s case for the possibility of noninferential
justication for theism proceeds on the basis of his Principle of Credulity, which says that if
it seems to S that p, then probably p. Applied to theistic belief, we get the result that theistic
seemings produced by religious experiences give us good evidence for theism. See Swin-
burne, The Existence of God, 292–327. For a sustained epistemological defense of this sort of
view, using the resources of phenomenal conservatism, see Tucker, “Phenomenal Conserva-
tism and Evidentialism in Religious Epistemology,” and McCain, “Evidence and Religious
Belief.”
21
For more sustained arguments for this, see Sudduth’s articles “Reformed Epistemology
and Christian Apologetics” and “Revisiting the ‘Reformed Objection’ to Natural Theology.”
Evans, Natural Signs and Knowledge of God, contains a developed religious epistemology
which explicitly includes roles for both Reformed Epistemology and natural theology.
22
See Plantinga, “Reply to Tooley’s Opening Statement,” 154–155.
Faith and Philosophy598
compatible with Reformed Epistemology and skeptical theism. Follow-
ing Scott Coley, let’s make a distinction between weak theodicy (typically
called “defense”) and strong theodicy (typically called “theodicy”).
23
A weak theodicy, or defense, is an explanation for some evil E which appeals
to some God-justifying reason R and says that, for all we know, R holds
and would justify God (if God exists) in permitting E. A strong theodicy
says that R does hold and that it justies God (if God exists) in permit-
ting E. A strong theodicist assumes that we have an ability to sometimes
identify those goods which would justify God in allowing certain evils.
Obviously, this is not incompatible with either the claim that (i) we have
non-inferential justication for belief in God or (ii) we have inferential jus-
tication for belief in God. The weak theodicist makes a weaker assump-
tion, namely that we have an ability to identify those goods which, if they
obtain, would justify God in permitting certain evils. Clearly, this claim
doesn’t conict with Reformed Epistemology or natural theology either.
If there is a good strong theodicy out there, then the theist can argue that
theism is non-inferentially justied and enjoys propositional support from
both natural theology and theodicy. And if there is a good weak theodicy
out there, the theist can say that theism enjoys non-inferential justication
and inferential justication (from natural theology), and that, owing to
weak theodicy, we can’t say whether E is propositional evidence against
theism or not. So, combining Reformed Epistemology with natural theol-
ogy and theodicy gives the theist a stronger response to the problem of
evil than she would have with any one or two of these alone. Now, I’m not
saying that there are any good theodicies. All I’m saying is that these three
options are compatible, and that if they all work, the theist who combines
them has a stronger response to the problem of evil than the theist who
only uses one or two of these strategies.
24
3. Skeptical Theism Plus Natural Theology Plus Theodicy
You can endorse everything I’ve said so far without thinking that the the-
ist’s overall epistemic situation is a very good one. For you might think
that theism gets some support from non-inferential sources, some from
natural theology, and some from theodicy, but that the total evidence still
favors some non-theistic hypothesis over theism. For instance, it might
be that there are some evils for which we have no theodicy and that the
negative evidence provided by these evils swamp the positive epistemic
support provided to theism by Reformed Epistemology, natural theology,
23
See Coley, “Skeptical Theism is Incompatible with Theodicy.”
24
It is interesting to note that Reformed Epistemologists and natural theologians have
both combined their favored approach to the justication of theistic belief with theodicy.
Plantinga, for instance, has defended a theodicy in his 2004 paper “Supralapsarianism, or
‘O Felix Culpa’”; Swinburne has done the same in his 1998 book Providence and the Problem
of Evil. Plantinga and Swinburne, then, seem to be committed to the compossibility of Re-
formed Epistemology, natural theology, and theodicy.
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 599
and theodicy. Skeptical theism, if applicable to the arguments from evil
that appeal to these evils, could help with this problem.
One potential problem for skeptical theism, however, is that it looks to
be incompatible with certain natural theological arguments. Wilks argues,
for instance, that skeptical theism assumes that we are unable to say that
any apparent evils are all-things-considered evil and hence not justied
by some greater good.
25
But if we cannot say this about evils, then we
cannot say this about goods. And if we cannot say that certain goods are
all-things-considered good, then we cannot say whether God would bring
about such goods. Wilks points out that this kind of skepticism would un-
dermine the design argument, for on this kind of skepticism we wouldn’t
be able to say whether the goods produced by an orderly universe would
be the sorts of things God would want to bring about.
26
A second potential problem for skeptical theism is that it looks to be
incompatible with theodicy. Coley explains why: any possible good G that
a theodicist might appeal to as an explanation for why God allows some
evil E will fall prey to the following skeptical theist claim: there might be
a good G* that is much greater than G and which entails the prevention of
E. If a theodicist is giving a strong theodicy, and she’s saying she knows
of a good G that really would justify God’s permission of E, then skepti-
cal theism will tell her that G might be outweighed by G*, which entails
the prevention of E. And if this theodicist is giving a weak theodicy (or a
defense), and she’s saying she knows of a possible good G which would
justify God’s permission of E, then—says Coley—she’s just doing what
the skeptical theist does, and her position reduces to that of the skeptical
theist. In short, weak theodicy, on Coley’s telling, is just a version of skep-
tical theism, which happens to be incompatible with strong theodicy.
So far, then, it looks like skeptical theism is incompatible with both nat-
ural theology and theodicy. The basic reason for this seeming incompati-
bility is that natural theology and theodicy appear to require the following
assumption: we are in a position to know (or at least justiedly believe),
at least in part, which things God would likely allow or produce in the
world. Call this the “likelihood assumption.”
27
Skeptical theism, however,
25
Wilks, “The Structure of the Contemporary Debate on the Problem of Evil.”
26
See Wilks, “The Structure of the Contemporary Debate on the Problem of Evil.” Wilks
doesn’t make his case on this point in terms of goods and evils being all-things-considered
good or evil. This is how Bergmann reconstructs Wilks’s argument, and in my presentation
of Wilks I follow Bergmann’s reconstruction. See Bergmann, “Skeptical Theism and the Prob-
lem of Evil,” 398.
27
The natural theologian, making the likelihood assumption, argues that certain goods
are quite likely on theism and hence that their existence is evidence for theism. The theo-
dicist, making the likelihood assumption, argues that certain goods which God is likely to
allow or produce logically require certain evils or their permission, and hence that the exis-
tence of these evils is not unlikely on theism (and may in fact even be likely on theism). See
Anderson, “Skeptical Theism and Value Judgments,” for a good argument that the distinc-
tion between an evil and its permission is (sometimes, at least) important. The basic point is
that it may be the case that an occurrence of an evil is all-things-considered bad, but that its
Faith and Philosophy600
rejects the likelihood assumption and tells us that we are not in a position
to know (or justiedly believe) what God would allow or bring about in
the world, thus undermining natural theology and theodicy. As Cullison
puts it, skeptical theism seems to imply that “any attempt to reason about
what God would do is in jeopardy.”
28
Following Cullison, let’s call this the
“Reasoning about God Problem,” or the “RAG problem” for short. Given
the RAG problem, it looks like the theist will have to choose between two
incompatible responses to the problem of evil, one which includes natural
theology and theodicy, and has room for Reformed Epistemology, and the
skeptical theist response, which also has room for Reformed Epistemol-
ogy but not for theodicy and natural theology. In the remainder of this sec-
tion, I will outline two possible responses to this dilemma, one concessive
and one non-concessive.
3.1. The Concessive Response
The concessive response concedes that skeptical theism and theodicy
are incompatible, but denies that skeptical theism is incompatible with
natural theology. A theist who adopts this response will be able to utilize
the resources of Reformed Epistemology, skeptical theism, and natural
theology, but not the resources of theodicy. The compatibility of skep-
tical theism, natural theology, and Reformed Epistemology falls short
of the claim I am ultimately aiming for here, but it’s an option worth
pausing to take note of.
As Wilks himself points out, skeptical theism does not make trouble
for all natural theological arguments.
29
The reason is that not all natural
theological arguments involve predicting that there is some good that God
would likely bring about and thus that theism is more likely given this
good. Some versions of some natural theological arguments, such as the
standard approach to the ne-tuning argument, do indeed involve making
likelihood assignments, i.e., saying that we can know or justiably believe
propositions about how likely some good or evil would be given theism.
Perhaps such arguments are out-of-bounds, given skeptical theism. Many
other natural theological arguments, however, don’t involve any likeli-
hood assignment and thus don’t require the likelihood assumption. Many
of Plantinga’s two dozen or so theistic arguments, for example, do not in-
volve any likelihood assignment at all. The ontological and cosmological
arguments don’t require any likelihood assignment, nor does the moral
argument. In general, the traditional, classical versions of the arguments
of natural theology are best thought of as metaphysical demonstrations of
the existence of a necessary being who serves as the ground of existence
rather than as abductive-style arguments to the effect that theism better
permission is not. It may be the case that God’s permission of an evil is necessary for some
outweighing good even if the occurrence of that evil is not.
28
Cullison, “Two New Versions of Skeptical Theism,” 250.
29
Wilks, “The Structure of the Contemporary Debate,” 317–318.
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 601
predicts certain facts than rival hypotheses.
30
Even the contemporary
version of the ne-tuning argument can be articulated without presup-
posing the likelihood assumption. William Lane Craig’s version of that
argument, for example, involves positing three possible explanations for
the ne-tuning—chance, necessity, or design—and then ruling out chance
and necessity, leaving design as the only plausible, or even possible, ex-
planation standing.
31
I’m not here endorsing (or even articulating) any
such arguments; I’m simply noting that many of the traditional arguments
of natural theology look to be fully compatible with skeptical theism in
that they don’t require making predictions about God’s behavior and thus
don’t require the likelihood assumption.
This is a good place to point out that it’s not clear that natural theolog-
ical arguments which say that some good is more likely on theism than
on some nontheistic hypothesis, such as naturalism, really do require the
likelihood assumption. If they don’t, then probabilistic natural theology
may well be out of the woods. Poston argues that our inability to say
whether some evil is gratuitous or not in no way imperils our knowledge
that certain things have value.
32
Using Swinburne’s examples, Poston argues that we know, for in-
stance, that consciousness and freedom are valuable. Following Poston,
let H stand for “humanly free creatures exist,” T for theism, and N for nat-
uralism. Given the value of consciousness and freedom, we can say that
the likelihood of H given T is not too low. We can also say that the likeli-
hood of H given N is low.
33
Thus, we can say that H is evidence for theism
over and against naturalism. Poston does concede—to Beaudoin
34
—that
the goods of consciousness and freedom “might also realize a disastrous
consequence that lies beyond our comprehension.” However, it could also
be that these goods lead to “unconceived felicitous consequences.” In the
end, then, these “unconceived values wash out,” leaving us with our orig-
inal judgment that H is more likely on theism than on naturalism.
35
Poston’s claim that the “unconceived values wash out” is not special
pleading for the theist. Poston is making essentially the same move that
30
There are also moral arguments which don’t involve likelihood assignments. Wolter-
storff, for example, argues that there is no adequate secular grounding of human rights and
then suggests that, given the existence of human rights and the existence of a plausible the-
istic grounding of such rights, we have a reason to believe theism. See Wolterstorff, Justice,
361ff.
31
See Craig, “Design and the Anthropic Fine-Tuning of the Universe.”
32
See Poston, “Skeptical Theism within Reason.”
33
According to Poston:
Naturalism doesn’t predict the existence of humanly free creatures. Why? There is noth-
ing about the content of the naturalist hypothesis that predicts H. Value considerations per-
taining to H play no role whatsoever in naturalism’s ability to account for H. According
to naturalism, H is the result of blind processes working over millions of years. It’s very
surprising that H would be true given naturalism.” (“Skeptical Theism within Reason,” 319)
34
See Beaudoin, “Evil, the Human Cognitive Condition, and Natural Theology.”
35
Poston, “Skeptical Theism within Reason,” 321.
Faith and Philosophy602
Draper makes in his Bayesian argument from evil. One of the premises in
this argument is that naturalism predicts “the data of good and evil” better
than theism does.
36
Draper concedes that “we should not be able to expect
to discern potentially God-justifying reasons for allowing the evils we nd
in the world.”
37
However, he does not think that this undermines his ability
to say that the data of good and evil are more likely on naturalism than
on theism. Our situation is this: we know that (i) the world’s evils are bad
and thus that God would have a reason to prevent them, (ii) there might be
God-justifying reasons for the world’s evils unknown to us, and (iii) there
could be reasons unknown to us for God to not create a world containing
the data of good and evil. Draper argues that, in this situation, “it is the
known reasons that must break the tie”—i.e., that our knowledge of the
badness of the world’s evils still gives us a reason to think that those evils
are less likely on theism than on naturalism.
38
In other words, when I know
that there might be unknown God-justifying reasons for preventing some
evil E, and also that there might be unknown God-justifying reasons for
allowing E, I can still say that E is less likely on theism than naturalism—for
“it is the known reasons that break the tie.” Poston makes this move, essen-
tially, when he argues that our unconceived reasons against bringing about
humanly free creatures and our unconceived reasons for bringing about
humanly free creatures “wash out,” leaving us with our original judgment
that God has a good reason to bring about humanly free creatures.
39
3.2. Non-Concessive Responses
I want to now argue that there are ways of combining skeptical theism
with both natural theology and theodicy. The core claim
40
of skeptical the-
ism is the following:
Skeptical Theism: We are not in a position to say how likely the facts of evil
are given theism.
One possible reason for thinking that skeptical theism is true is simply
that we are beings with limited cognitive ability.
41
Given our cognitive
36
Draper, “Explanation and the Problem of Evil,” 72.
37
Draper, “Explanation and the Problem of Evil,” 79.
38
Draper, “Explanation and the Problem of Evil,” 77.
39
I’ve discussed Poston’s views in a section on concessive responses because it suited
my dialectical purposes to do so, but I should note that this does not mean that I think that
Poston himself would endorse the concessive response over the non-concessive response. As
a referee points out, Poston’s views in fact seem to fall into the non-concessive camp. I agree
and thank the referee for helping to clear up any confusion on this point.
40
As Bergmann notes, skeptical theism has a theistic component and a skeptical compo-
nent. A nontheist could embrace the skeptical component without embracing the theistic
component. So, weirdly, a nontheist can be a skeptical theist, of sorts. See Bergman, “Skepti-
cal Theism and the Problem of Evil,” 375.
41
For more on our cognitive limitations, and how those prevent us from being in a posi-
tion to see why God would allow the particular evils he does (if he exists), see Alston, “The
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 603
limitations we have good reasons to be very humble when thinking about
the likelihood of some instance of evil given theism. Consider, in this vein,
Bergmann’s skeptical thesis, ST4:
ST4: We have no good reason for thinking that the total moral value or dis-
value we perceive in certain complex states of affairs accurately reects the
total moral value or disvalue they really have.
42
Call this “state of affairs skepticism.” Anyone who endorses state of affairs
skepticism has a good reason to think that she is in no position to afrm
the reliability of her seeming that some instance of evil E is not part of a
larger complex state of affairs which is overall good and which defeats E.
State of affairs skepticism seems quite plausible, at least in this respect:
our cognitive limitations are such that it is very difcult, perhaps even
impossible, for us say whether the value we seem to perceive in a complex
state of affairs accurately reects the total value in that state of affairs, or
in some larger, even more complex state of affairs in which the state of
affairs under consideration is a part. So, for example, I can see that S’s
having cancer is bad, but I can’t see that S’s having cancer isn’t part of a
larger complex state of affairs that is overall good and defeats the badness
of S’s having cancer. If I am aware of my own cognitive limitations on the
matter, then I have a defeater for any seeming to the effect that God’s al-
lowance of S’s having cancer is unlikely: if S’s having cancer is in fact part
of a larger complex state of affairs in which it is defeated by some good G,
and if God strongly desires that G be brought about, then it may be quite
likely that God would allow S’s having cancer.
It should be obvious, though still important to take note of, that state
of affairs skepticism is not incompatible with Reformed Epistemology’s
claim that we can have non-inferential justication for theistic belief, nor
with the natural theologian’s claim that we can have inferential justica-
tion for God’s existence—the ontological and cosmological arguments, for
example, are unaffected by the sort of skepticism at play in Bergmann’s
ST4. ST4 does, promisingly, seem to undercut arguments from evil that
appeal to tokens or instances of evil, for we cannot say whether any given
token of evil is or is not part of a larger complex state of affairs which is
overall very good and which defeats the token evil in question. But does
ST4 allow for theodicy?
If we make a distinction between tokens of evil and types of evil, we
might open a path to combining skeptical theism and theodicy by arguing
that we can be skeptical theists about arguments from evil that appeal
to tokens of evil while offering theodicies in response to arguments from
evil that appeal to types of evil. The basic idea is that while we may be
in a position to say which types of evil-requiring goods God would allow
Inductive Argument from Evil and the Human Cognitive Condition”; Howard-Snyder, “The
Argument from Inscrutable Evil”; and Poston, “Skeptical Theism Within Reason.”
42
Bergmann, “Skeptical Theism and the Problem of Evil,” 379.
Faith and Philosophy604
or produce in a world, we cannot say, of any token instance of evil, how
likely that particular token is given theism. So, we can make rough likeli-
hood assignments about types of evil, but not about tokens of evil. On this
approach, I may be able to offer a theodicy for animal suffering in general
without being able to explain why God allowed Rowe’s fawn to suffer
and die in that forest re. This approach opens the door to combining
skeptical theism with full-bore probabilistic natural theology: skepticism
about tokens can be combined with the non-skeptical thought that God
would likely allow or bring about certain types of goods in a world, such
as a world governed according to laws of nature, or a world with rational
creatures who can appreciate beauty, and so on.
This approach to combining skeptical theism with theodicy and natural
theology makes use of the following idea:
Token Skepticism: Having an explanation for a type of evil does not entail
having an explanation for a token of that type.
By combining token skepticism and skeptical theism we get a view we
can call “token skeptical theism.” As I read van Inwagen’s Gifford Lec-
tures on the problem of evil, he endorses token skepticism.
43
Someone
who embraces token skepticism is free to endorse or reject the idea that
God would allow gratuitous evil.
44
If a token skeptical theist embraces the
compatibility of theism and gratuitous evil, then she can say, in response
to an argument from evil that appeals to a particular instance of evil E,
that E may well, for all we know, be gratuitous. So, if E is Rowe’s fawn suf-
fering and dying in a forest re, this token skeptical theist can reply that
E’s possible gratuitousness is not incompatible with theism. And on the
assumption that gratuitous evil is compatible with theism, it will be very
difcult to say how likely E is on theism, thereby providing a response to
a probabilistic argument from evil that says that E, while perhaps com-
patible with theism, is very unlikely on theism. Of course, it may initially
seem to us that E isn’t very likely on theism. But once we realize that we
are in no position to say how likely particular tokens of evil are on theism,
because having an explanation for E-type evils doesn’t entail having an
explanation for any particular E-type token of evil, we gain a defeater: our
seeming that E isn’t likely on theism loses its justicatory juice (and this
holds even if that seeming persists).
I should note what is perhaps obvious: namely, that the view that gratu-
itous evil is compatible with theism in no way implies the much stronger
and implausible view that theism is compatible with all evil being gratu-
itous. Rather, the idea would be that some evil is permitted for the sake
of a greater good and yet that God is morally justied in permitting other
43
See van Inwagen, The Problem of Evil.
44
For defenses of the compatibility of theism and gratuitous evil, see Hasker, “The Neces-
sity of Gratuitous Evil,” and Howard-Snyder and Howard-Snyder, “Is Theism Compatible
with Gratuitous Evil?”
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 605
evils even though no greater good necessitates them (nor are such evils
necessary for the prevention of an even worse evil). If something like this
were true, then it would open the door to the following sort of view. If we
can’t think of a God-justifying reason for some evil, then maybe that evil
is gratuitous. But we can think of a God-justifying reason for some evils,
hence some evils can be explained and some cannot. You might think that
this is, in fact, a decent approximation of our actual cognitive situation on
these matters: we can explain some but not all evils, and our inability to
explain all evils is due in part to the fact that our world contains gratu-
itous evils. The possibility that some evils may be gratuitous while others
are not helps to explain why the compossibility of theism and gratuitous
evil does not render skeptical theism superuous. Evils that we cannot
explain may be gratuitous or they may have explanations that lie beyond
our ken. Gratuitous evils are not thereby unjustied, we should note; so, a
skeptical theist retort is not superuous here: “I don’t know of a theodicy
that covers evil E,” a theist might say. “It may be that E is explained by a
good that lies beyond my ken, or it may be that E is justied even though
it is gratuitous. Either way, my inability to explain E does not imply that
it is unjustied.”
But, of course, a token skeptical theist doesn’t have to endorse the com-
patibility of theism and gratuitous evil. A token skeptical theist who re-
jects gratuitous evil can say that any seeming that God would not allow
E because E is apparently gratuitous is defeated by the realization that
we aren’t in a position to say that E is gratuitous. I might have a good ex-
planation for E-type evils without having a good explanation for E itself,
assuming token skepticism. E isn’t explainable by my theodicy for E-type
evils, but it might be explainable by some other theodicy, maybe one I’m
currently not aware of. I can’t say that E is gratuitous simply because I’m
not aware of any good, God-justifying explanation for it. In light of the
foregoing, I am likely to be in the dark about the likelihood of E given the-
ism. If I have a good theodicy for E-type evils, then I won’t be in the dark
about them even if I’m in the dark about E itself: skeptical theism about
tokens seems to t comfortably with theodicy about types.
What if the atheologian in question, instead of claiming that E is gratu-
itous, argues in Draper-style that E is unlikely on theism but not on some
alternative hypothesis? Here, a token skeptical theist, who rejects gratu-
itous evil, can simply say that we aren’t in a position to say how likely
tokens of evil like E are on theism due to the fact that explaining a type of
evil doesn’t imply explaining all instances of that type—and that, again,
this holds even if we have a good theodicy for E-type evils in general. Of
course, it may well be that having a theodicy for E-type evils raises the
probability of E itself. But that, of course, doesn’t in turn imply that we can
say how likely E is on theism. Perhaps the best we can say here is that, in
light of our theodicy for E-type evils, E itself isn’t too unlikely on theism.
Given token skepticism, it may well be that E is explained by some theo-
dicy other than the one we have for E-type evils in general, one which is
Faith and Philosophy606
beyond our ken. In any case, the general idea here is that, since a theodicy
for a type of evil doesn’t necessarily account for every token of that type,
arguments from evil that appeal to a particular instance of evil will run
headlong into the token skeptical theist’s claim that we are not very good
at judging the likelihood of tokens of evil.
45
One crucial question here is whether we should embrace token
skeptical theism in the rst place. Maybe it’s not a very good view. As
I indicated above, a full articulation and defense of the view isn’t possi-
ble here, but it’s worth noting that there may well be an asymmetry here
between explanations of non-agential happenings and explanations of
agential happenings. If I’ve got an explanation for why, in general, water
freezes when it gets below a certain temperature, then it looks like I’ve got
an explanation of any particular instance of water freezing. Here, in the
non- agential realm, it looks like having an explanation for a type may well
entail having an explanation for every token of that type. The same may
not be said, however, for happenings in the agential realm. I may correctly
surmise that you let your daughter stay up late on Friday nights because
she doesn’t have school the next day. However, that explanation may not
hold for every single Friday night. Perhaps this Friday you planned on
putting her to bed early because she has somewhere to be early the next
morning, but due to some medicine she took, which makes it difcult to
sleep, you’re letting her stay up late this Friday night.
Skeptical theisms based on token skepticism sit well with the idea that
probabilistic natural theology arguments are, properly understood, really
about types of goods rather than tokens of those types. Recall Poston’s
H—humanly free creatures exist. Theists (or some of them, anyway) think
that H is not too low given theism due to the intrinsic value possessed
by consciousness and freedom. What such theists think, properly under-
stood, is that God would likely bring about a world containing things of a
certain type; theists don’t think that God would bring about any one par-
ticular humanly free creature, or homo sapiens specically. So, for instance,
my existence is not something anyone would predict as likely given the-
ism, but the existence of beings like me does seem—or so the argument
could go—likely given theism. The same line of thinking, i.e., of thinking
45
I intend what I am saying to be compatible with the claim that, in some cases, having
an explanation for a certain type of evil might entail having an explanation for every token
of that type. Suppose, for instance, that animals do not feel morally relevant pain and also
that animal pain is in general quite biologically useful; in such a case, God would have good
reasons to allow animal pain and no good reason not to. It might then follow, at least on the
assumption that there is no other morally sufcient reason to eliminate or minimize animal
pain, that we have an explanation for animal pain in general that covers every instance of
animal pain. Though I think this view is plausible, I am not endorsing it, but am merely call-
ing it to our attention as a potential example of the possibility of having an explanation for a
type of evil that covers every token of that type. For a recent argument against the idea that
animals do indeed feel morally relevant pain, see Miller, “Do Animals Feel Pain in a Morally
Relevant Sense?”
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 607
about what God would allow or bring about in terms of types rather than
tokens, seems to apply to how theists are thinking (or should be thinking)
when they do theodicy. In offering the free will theodicy as an explanation
for moral evil, for example, the theist isn’t saying that any one particular
token of morally bad action is necessary to secure the good of free will
in general. Rather, theists are arguing, or should understand themselves
to be arguing, that a good of a certain type necessitates God’s allowance
of evils of a certain type. In sum, when giving probabilistic natural theo-
logical arguments, the theist is best understood as arguing that it’s likely
that God would actualize a world with certain types of goods; and when
giving a theodicy, the theist is best understood as arguing that goods of
a certain type require the permission of evils of a certain type. This more
holistic approach seems to offer an answer to Cullison’s RAG problem: we
can reason fairly well about the types of things God would allow or bring
about, but not very well about which particular tokens of those types God
would allow or bring about.
Another worry about a version of the holistic response based on token
skepticism is that it is based on a misunderstanding of theodicy, for no
theodicist—someone might argue—claims to have good explanations for
all the particular tokens of evil we are confronted with.
46
Whether this is
true for any given theodicist will depend in part on whether that theod-
icist thinks that a theodicy for every type of evil explains every token of
that type. The worrier here seems to assume that no theodicist has ever
made that assumption, but I doubt whether that is true or not. In personal
conversation with me, both Plantinga and Swinburne argued that having
a theodicy for a type does entail having an explanation for every token of
that type. Also in personal conversation, Draper suggested the opposite,
arguing that having a theodicy for a type does not entail having a theodicy
for every token of that type. Given this, as well as the paucity of explicit
discussion of the matter, it is likely that the worrier’s assumption on this
score may well be false. Critics of theodicies sometimes respond to theod-
icies by pointing out that a proposed theodicy doesn’t explain all the facts
of evil. Laura Ekstrom, for example, says the following:
[O]ur experiences of, and awareness of, facts about evil in the world provide
awfully good reason to doubt that a hybrid case will succeed in covering
the full range, distribution, and intensity of evils. It seems especially unrea-
sonable to think that the pain endured by all sentient non-human animals
by way of neglect, abuse, torture, disease, and natural disaster can be justi-
ed by a hybrid theodicy that draws on the values of free will, punishment,
character- building, and connection with God.
47
Ekstrom’s complaint seems to presuppose or at least be consistent with
the idea that a theodicy for a type doesn’t cover every token of that type.
46
Thanks to a referee for helping me see the need to address this issue.
47
Ekstrom, God, Suffering and the Value of Free Will, 94–95.
Faith and Philosophy608
I think, then, that the matter is a contested one and thus that the objector
here is not justied in claiming that no theodicist claims to have good
explanations for all the particular tokens of evil we are confronted with.
But regardless of what theodicists do or do not assume about the scope
of their theodicy projects, it remains open to the atheologian to make ar-
guments from evil that appeal to types or tokens. And of course it remains
open to a critic of theodicy, someone such as Ekstrom, to complain that
extant theodicies don’t explain all the facts about evil. So, in response to
atheological arguments from evil in general, it is good for the theist to
have at her disposal responses to both types of argument, and thus it is
important to distinguish them and to note the possibility of offering a
skeptical theist reply to arguments from evil that appeal to tokens and to
offer a theodicy reply to arguments from evil that appeal to types. And in
response to complaints about the explanatory inadequacy of a theodicy,
it can be very useful to make use of the holistic response described here
by replying with skeptical theism about tokens and theodicy about types.
Other sorts of non-concessive holistic responses seem possible, at least
in principle. Let me briey outline, without developing, three of them.
For starters, you might simply think that we can explain some but not all
evils. For example, perhaps you are persuaded by Stump’s theodicy and
thus think we can explain the suffering of fully functional adult human
beings but also that we currently have no good explanation for the suffer-
ing of sentient beings, human or otherwise, that fall outside the scope of
this theodicy. Or perhaps you propagate what Ekstrom refers to as a “hy-
brid theodicy,” in which you offer different theodicies for different evils;
even with a hybrid theodicy on hand, however, you might still think that
you cannot explain every type of evil, or at least every token of every
type.
48
You might also think that, in virtue of having good inferential and/
or noninferential reasons to believe that God exists, and that God would
not allow an evil without having a justifying reason for doing so, that
God does have such reasons and thus that your inability to think of them
is not evidence that they aren’t there. This move would be a version of
what Rowe refers to as the “G. E. Moore shift.” The skeptical theism here
would be based on the fact that you have good reasons to think that God
exists and would not allow pointless evil. It could of course be helpfully
48
Ekstrom:
This raises the question of the plausibility of a hybrid theodicy or a bundle case.
Perhaps a theist could argue that, for some cases of evil, the God-justifying reason
for causing or allowing them is punishment, whereas with other cases of evil, the
God-justifying reason for allowing them is the preservation of created beings’ power
of libertarian free will, whereas in other cases of evil, the God-justifying reason for
causing or allowing them is temporally extended character development, and in
other cases of evil, the God-justifying reason for causing or allowing them is that
they provide avenues to knowledge of, and intimacy with, God. (God, Suffering, and
the Value of Free Will, 91)
I should note that Ekstrom does not here endorse this approach herself.
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 609
buttressed by reections on the limitations of human cognition in general
but also on the fact that you do have some explanations for some evils.
The skeptical theist bit in all this is, of course, the thought that an inability
to think of a God-justifying reason for evil E is no reason to think that there
is no such reason. Is it even reasonable to demand that theists be able to
produce explanations for every evil, or the exact amount of evil, and so
on? In how many domains of inquiry, for example, can we explain every
factum that is, in principle, explainable? To demand universal explana-
tions in this case seems like overkill, given our cognitive limitations; more
strongly, it seems like special pleading on behalf of religious skepticism.
Another possibility is that of being a skeptical theist qua generic theism
but a theodicist qua religious theism. So, suppose you endorse the view
that we have good inferential and/or noninferential reasons to think that
God exists. Qua generic theist, you might say that we aren’t able to explain
why God allows evil but that this is no reason to think that there aren’t any
such explanations at all. One reason for denying that we have the ability
to predict God’s behavior, qua generic theists, is that you might not think
of God as a well-behaved moral agent, that is, as someone who is subject
to and perfectly follows the same moral law that govern us. Without de-
nying divine goodness, you might take the line that that goodness does
not consist in being a well-behaved moral agent and thus that your ability
to predict divine behavior is not particularly strong. In their own ways,
Brian Davies, Mark Murphy, and Edward Feser have all recently given ar-
guments against the view that we should think of God as a well-behaved
moral agent.
49
But you might not be just a generic theist, for you—like
Davies, Murphy, and Feser—might also be a religious theist, that is, an
adherent to a theistic religion that posits divine revelation. You might then
say that, given the additional resources provided by divine revelation, we
can offer good theodicies for evil. So, if the atheologian wants to attack ge-
neric theism and you are content to operate just with the tools provided by
natural reason, you might respond by combining Reformed Epistemology,
natural theology, and skeptical theism. On the other hand, if the atheo-
logian wants to attack a specic version of religious theism, the one you
advance, you might then reply by combining Reformed Epistemology,
natural theology, and theodicy, bringing in the additional resources made
available to you by your faith tradition.
Yet another option involves making a distinction between non-
comparative probability judgments (“X is unlikely [likely] given the-
ism”) and comparative ones (“X is more likely [unlikely] on naturalism
than on theism”).
50
Skeptical theism might rule out non-comparative
probability judgments, meaning we can’t say how likely (full stop) ne-
tuning is, given theism, nor can we say how likely (full stop) some evil
49
See Davies, The Reality of God and the Problem of Evil, 84–105; Murphy, God’s Own Ethics,
106–116; Feser, “The Thomistic Dissolution of the Logical Problem of Evil.”
50
Thanks to a referee for pointing out the possibility of this version of the holistic response.
Faith and Philosophy610
E is given theism. But this seems compatible with being able to say that
ne- tuning, say, is more likely on theism than naturalism. I may not be
able to say how likely it is that the U.S. Congress will declare war on X,
but I know that it is more likely that they will declare war on X than it
is that Vice-President Harris will declare war on X (for the simple rea-
son that vice-presidents don’t have the authority to declare war). The
ruling out of non-comparative probability judgments also seems com-
patible with saying, in Draper-style, that some evil E is more likely on,
say, the hypothesis of indifference than it is on theism. So, this version of
the non- concessive holistic response allows the theist to wield skeptical
theism against non-comparative likelihood judgments of the sort, “evil E
is evidence against theism because it is unlikely given theism”; in reply,
the skeptical theist will argue we are in the dark about the likelihood
of E given theism. Draper-style comparative arguments from evil would
have to be met with another response, but there’s no in-principle reason
to think that one or more of the other elements of the holistic response
couldn’t be brought in for that job.
4. Conclusion
The holistic response to evil would not be a silver bullet. There is no
guarantee that theists will be able to come up with good theodicies; no
guarantee that the arguments of natural theology work; no guarantee that
skeptical theism can be defended from the serious objections which have
been leveled against it, such as that it implies too much skepticism; and no
guarantee that we really can have noninferential justication for theistic
belief. Theists will still have to do—or, rather, keep doing—the hard work
of defending each of the four standard responses to the problem of evil.
However, the result reached here is not insignicant. If the four standard
theistic responses to the problem of evil are in fact compatible, then, so
long as each one is defensible in its own right, it suggests that the theist
has at her disposal a powerful, holistic response to what is perhaps the
most serious objection to God’s existence.
Conception Seminary College
References
Alston, William. 1991. “The Inductive Argument from Evil and the Human Cog-
nitive Condition.” Philosophical Perspectives 5: 29–67. https://doi.org/10.2307
/2214090.
Anderson, David. 2012. “Skeptical Theism and Value Judgments.” International
Journal for Philosophy of Religion 72: 27–39. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153
-012-9358-1.
Baker-Hytch, Max. 2023. “Natural Theology and Religious Belief.” In The Cambridge
Handbook of Religious Epistemology, edited by Jonathan Fuqua, John Greco, and
Tyler McNabb (Cambridge University Press), 13–28.
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 611
Beaudoin, John. 1998. “Evil, the Human Cognitive Condition, and Natural Theol-
ogy.” Religious Studies 34: 403–418. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0034412598004557.
Bergmann, Michael. 2001. “Skeptical Theism and Rowe’s New Evidential Argu-
ment from Evil.” Nous 35: 278–296. https://doi.org/10.1111/0029-4624.00297.
Bergmann, Michael. 2009. “Skeptical Theism and the Problem of Evil.” In The
Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology, edited by Michael Rea and Thomas
Flint (Oxford University Press), 374–399.
Bergmann, Michael. 2012. “Rational Religious Belief Without Argument.” In
Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology, 6th ed., edited by Michael Rea and Louis
Pojman (Cengage Learning), 534–549.
Bergmann, Michael. 2023. “Reformed Epistemology.” In The Cambridge Handbook
of Religious Epistemology, edited by Jonathan Fuqua, John Greco, and Tyler
McNabb (Cambridge University Press), 41–55.
Coley, Scott. 2015. “Skeptical Theism is Incompatible with Theodicy.” International
Journal for Philosophy of Religion 77: 53–63. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153
-014-9494-x.
Craig, William Lane. 2003. “Design and the Anthropic Fine-Tuning of the Uni-
verse.” In God and Design: The Teleological Argument and Modern Science, edited
by Neil Manson (Routledge), 155–177.
Craig, William Lane, and J. P. Moreland, eds. 2009. The Blackwell Companion to
Natural Theology (Wiley-Blackwell).
Cullison, Andrew. 2014. “Two New Versions of Skeptical Theism.” In Skeptical
Theism: New Essays, edited by Trent Dougherty and Justin McBrayer (Oxford
University Press), 250–263.
Davies, Brian. 2006. The Reality of God and the Problem of Evil (Continuum).
Dougherty, Trent. 2014. “Skeptical Theism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philoso-
phy (Spring 2014 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu
/archives/spr2014/entries/skeptical-theism.
Dougherty, Trent, and Chris Tweedt. 2015. “Religious Epistemology.” Philosophy
Compass 10: 547–559. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12185.
Draper, Paul. 1989. “Pain and Pleasure: An Evidential Problem for Theists.” Nous
23: 331–350. https://doi.org/10.2307/2215486.
Draper, Paul. 1996. “The Skeptical Theist.” In The Evidential Argument from Evil,
edited by Daniel Howard-Snyder (Indiana University Press), 175–192.
Draper, Paul. 2009. “The Problem of Evil.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical
Theology, edited by Thomas Flint and Michael Rea (Oxford University Press),
332–351.
Draper, Paul. 2013. “Explanation and the Problem of Evil.” In The Blackwell
Companion to the Problem of Evil, edited by Daniel Howard-Snyder and Justin
McBrayer (Wiley-Blackwell), 71–79.
Ekstrom, Laura. 2021. God, Suffering, and the Value of Free Will (Oxford University
Press).
Evans, C. Stephen. 2010. Natural Signs and Knowledge of God: A New Look at Theistic
Arguments (Oxford University Press).
Feser, Edward. 2017. Five Proofs of the Existence of God (Ignatius Press).
Feser, Edward. 2021. “The Thomistic Dissolution of the Logical Problem of Evil.”
Religions 12: 268. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12040268.
Hasker, William. 1992. “The Necessity of Gratuitous Evil.” Faith and Philosophy
9: 23–44. https://doi.org/10.5840/faithphil1992911.
Hick, John. 2010. Evil and the God of Love, 3
rd
ed. (Palgrave Macmillan).
Faith and Philosophy612
Holley, David. 2010. “Treating God’s Existence as an Explanatory Hypothesis.”
American Philosophical Quarterly 47: 377–388. https://www.jstor.org/stable
/25734163.
Howard-Snyder, Daniel. 1996. “The Argument from Inscrutable Evil.” In The
Evidential Argument from Evil, edited by Daniel Howard-Snyder (Indiana
University Press), 286–310.
Howard-Snyder, Daniel. 2013. “The Logical Problem of Evil: Mackie and Plant-
inga.” In The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, edited by Daniel
Howard-Snyder and Justin McBrayer (Wiley-Blackwell), 19–33.
Howard-Snyder, Daniel, and Frances Howard-Snyder. 1999. “Is Theism Compati-
ble with Gratuitous Evil?” American Philosophical Quarterly 36: 115–130. https://
www.jstor.org/stable/20009958.
McBrayer, Justin. 2010. “Skeptical Theism.” Philosophy Compass 5: 611–623. https://
doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00306.x.
McCain, Kevin. 2023. “Evidence and Religious Belief.” In The Cambridge Hand-
book of Religious Epistemology, edited by Jonathan Fuqua, John Greco, and Tyler
McNabb (Cambridge University Press), 29–40.
McNabb, Tyler. 2015. “Warranted Religion: Answering Objections to Alvin Plant-
inga’s Epistemology.” Religious Studies 51: 477–495. https://doi.org/10.1017
/s003441251400033x.
Miller, Calum. 2021. “Do Animals Feel Pain in a Morally Relevant Sense?” Philoso-
phia 49: 373–392. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-020-00254-x.
Moon, Andrew. 2016. “Recent Work in Reformed Epistemology.” Philosophy Com-
pass 11: 879–891. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12361.
Murphy, Mark. 2017. God’s Own Ethics: Norms of Divine Agency and the Argument
from Evil (Oxford University Press).
Murray, Michael. 2009. “Theodicy.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology,
edited by Michael Rea and Thomas Flint (Oxford University Press), 352–373.
Pike, Nelson. 1963. “Hume on Evil.” The Philosophical Review 72: 180–197. https://
doi.org/10.2307/2183103.
Plantinga, Alvin. 1967. God and Other Minds (Cornell University Press).
Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. The Nature of Necessity (Clarendon Press).
Plantinga, Alvin. 1981. “The Reformed Objection to Natural Theology.” Proceed-
ings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 15: 49–62. https://doi
.org/10.5840/acpaproc1980547.
Plantinga, Alvin. 1990. God and Other Minds, rev. ed. (Cornell University Press).
Plantinga, Alvin. 1996. “On Being Evidentially Challenged.” In The Evidential Argument
from Evil, edited by Daniel-Howard Snyder (Indiana University Press), 244–261.
Plantinga, Alvin. 2000. Warranted Christian Belief (Oxford University Press).
Plantinga, Alvin. 2004. “Supralapsarianism, or ‘O Felix Culpa.’” In Christian Faith
and the Problem of Evil, edited by Peter van Inwagen (Eerdmans), 1–25.
Plantinga, Alvin. 2007. “Two Dozen (or so) Theistic Arguments.” In Alvin Plant-
inga, edited by Deane Peter-Baker (Cambridge University Press), 203–227.
Plantinga, Alvin. 2008. “Reply to Tooley’s Opening Statement.” In Knowledge of
God, by Alvin Plantinga and Michael Tooley (Wiley-Blackwell), 151–183.
Plantinga, Alvin. 2011. Where the Conict Really Lies (Oxford University Press).
Plantinga, Alvin, and Michael Tooley. 2008. Knowledge of God (Wiley-Blackwell).
Poston, Ted. 2014. “Skeptical Theism within Reason.” In Skeptical Theism: New
Essays, edited by Trent Dougherty and Justin McBrayer (Oxford University
Press), 307–322.
A HOLISTIC RESPONSE TO EVIL 613
Robinson, Thaddeus. 2013. “Descartes’s Sceptical Theism.” Religious Studies 49:
515–527. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0034412512000418.
Rowe, William. 1979. “The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism.” American
Philosophical Quarterly 16: 335–341. https://www.jstor.org/stable/20009775.
Rudavsky, T. M. 2013. “A Brief History of Skeptical Responses to Evil.” In The
Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, edited by Daniel Howard-Snyder and
Justin McBrayer (Wiley-Blackwell), 379–395.
Schellenberg, John. 2013. “A New Logical Problem of Evil.” In The Blackwell
Companion to the Problem of Evil, edited by Daniel Howard-Snyder and Justin
McBrayer (Wiley-Blackwell), 34–48.
Sterba, James P. 2019. Is a Good God Logically Possible? (Palgrave Macmillan).
Stump, Eleonore. 1996. “Aquinas on the Sufferings of Job.” In The Evidential
Argument from Evil, edited by Daniel Howard-Snyder (Indiana University
Press), 49–68.
Stump, Eleonore. 2010. Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering
(Oxford University Press).
Sudduth, Michael. 2003. “Reformed Epistemology and Christian Apologetics.”
Religious Studies 39: 299–321. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034412503006553.
Sudduth, Michael. 2009. “Revisiting the ‘Reformed Objection’ to Natural
Theology.” European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 2: 37–62. https://doi.org
/10.24204/ejpr.v1i2.340.
Swinburne, Richard. 1998. Providence and the Problem of Evil (Oxford University
Press).
Swinburne, Richard. 2004. The Existence of God, 2nd ed. (Oxford University Press).
Swinburne, Richard. 2005. Faith and Reason, 2nd ed. (Oxford University Press).
Tucker, Chris. 2011. “Phenomenal Conservatism and Evidentialism in Religious
Epistemology.” In Evidence and Religious Belief, edited by Kelly James Clark and
Raymond J. VanArragon (Oxford University Press), 52–73.
van Inwagen, Peter. 2006. The Problem of Evil (Oxford University Press).
Walls, Jerry, and Trent Dougherty. 2018. Two Dozen (or So) Arguments for God: The
Plantinga Project (Oxford University Press).
Wilks, Ian. 2004. “The Structure of the Contemporary Debate on the Problem of Evil.”
Religious Studies 40: 307–321. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0034412504006900.
Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 2008. Justice: Rights and Wrongs (Princeton University Press.)